Hard, Soft and Non-Problems of Absurdity: A Marxian Critique of Thomas Nagel’s Understanding of the Absurd








Hard, Soft and Non-Problems of Absurdity

A Marxian Critique of Thomas Nagel’s Understanding of the Absurd

Farid Saberi

Author’s note: This is a working draft. Please share with me your comments and feedback at this email: fsaberi2@uwo.ca

For the pdf version of the paper, click here 

Contents

Introduction

Section One: Nagel on folk and philosophical absurdity

1-1 folk absurdity: arguments from minuteness

1-2 folk absurdity: arguments from “chain of actions-justification”

1-3 philosophical absurdity

1-4. Solutions for philosophical absurdity

Section Two: Problems of Nagel’s Ironic Absurdism

2-1 Where the folk understanding of absurdity does not fail?

2-2 The failed distinction between conventional and philosophical absurdity

2.3. Hard, Soft and Non-Problem of Absurdity

Section Three: Against Heroism and liberal Irony

Conclusion: Socialist Humor Against Liberal Irony

 

Introduction

In October 1971, Tom Nagel, one of the most prominent analytical philosophers of the time, presented a talk in the annual meeting of the American Philosophical Association titled “The Absurd.” Later, this talk was published in the Journal of Philosophy as a short 12-page paper. Nagel probably had no idea, when writing the line of his paper, that more than 50 years later, how much readers of his paper (us) will find his arguments deeply resonating. Readers rendered desperate and helpless by an increasingly absurd age and hit by the political and economic crises.  

Central to the concept of the Absurd, as Nagel understands it, is a discrepancy between what we expect from reality and how reality actually behaves. And who can deny that such discrepancies have become dominant features of our time of protracted economic and political crisis.  We are living in a strange and weird era.  One cannot be sure where to draw the line between serious and ridiculous aspects of their personal and social life. The rise of far-right in the West and the assault of populist bigotry on the political establishment (already corrupted by a liberal elite) in the absence of a militant labor party, has created grotesque scenes. Words that Marx used for describing the political upheavals after the second republic (1848) in France and the rise of Louis Bonaparte (a populist Trump-like figure of the day) are very apt and resonate with our day and age.

“The period that we have before us comprises the most motley mixture of crying contradictions ... alliances whose first proviso is separation; struggles whose first law is indecision; wild, inane agitation in the name of tranquility, most solemn preaching of tranquility in the name of revolution – passions without truth, truths without passion; heroes without heroic deeds, history without events.” (Marx, The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte, Ch 3)

Alongside this absurd and contradictory socio-political reality, it is also hard to not notice the absurdities in our personal lives. The precarious labor market and increasing redistribution of wealth and income from the public and lower classes to the elite in neoliberalized capitalism has created a deep discrepancy between what we expect to be a minimally stable, peaceful, and fulfilled personal and professional life and what our lives actually go through. Ridiculous! Absurd! These are phrases that most of us increasingly find ourselves telling ourselves in the middle of our daily busy lives, and its daily frustrations and uncertainties.

If there is ever a proper (even urgent) time to think philosophically and deeply about the concept of the absurd, it is now. In his paper, Nagel tries something that was not customary for the philosophical establishment of the day. He used conceptual analysis and other analytical tools and applied them to uncharted territories for the analytical tradition. Instead of classical and well-informed metaphysical problems of the anglophone philosophy (questions of mind, language and free will), he approached the unorthodox question of “The Absurd.” He criticizes Camus’s understanding of the term and proposes his own definition and understanding of the term. Using the clear and argumentative style of analytical philosophers, he makes accessible the crux of the philosophical problem of the absurdity. This stands in contrast to that flamboyant literary and phenomenological jargon of some existentialist writers where lucidity is not always a priority.

My argument here is two-fold. I agree with Nagel that the folk experience of absurdity and the way this experience is conceptually articulated (“the standard arguments for absurdity”) is distorted and confused. However, I argue that his proposed philosophical articulation of the absurd is not coherent and deprives the folk experience of the absurd from its true and original crux hidden behind its confused expressions. Here, firstly, I review the main argument of Nagel’s paper and compare his liberal “ironic view” of absurdity to Camus’s “heroic view.’ (Sect 1). Then, I highlight some inconsistencies in his argument and some difficulties in his account (Sect. 2). Finally, I distinguish between three problems of absurdity (hard, soft, and non-problem) and I will propose a eudemonic approach to absurdity (Sect. 3). I conclude by discussing socialist humor, liberal ironic or heroic attitudes to absurdity (Sect. 3).

Section One: Nagel on folk and philosophical absurdity

1-1 folk absurdity: arguments from minuteness

Standard and folk understanding of the absurdity of the human life, as Nagel understands it, can be described as arguments from minuteness. Minuteness is supposed to mean the cosmic insignificance of human personal and social concerns, aspirations, and struggles. Consider these 3 versions of the argument from minuteness:

a.     Nothing that we deeply care about, and we do matter because a million years from now (when even our species is not around), none of these staff will be relevant or matter.

b.     Nothing that we do matters given how small and insignificant we are in this incredibly vast universe.

c.     Nothing that we do matters given how fragile and contingent finite human life is, namely, a life that is always threatened by the possibility of death.

Nagel, like any other good, dry and prosaic analytical philosopher, questions the logical entailment of these claims. He argues that whether something matters or not is independent from contingencies of time, space and death. In other words, X could matter (or not matter) now and continue to matter for a certain duration and then stop existing. The fact that a million years from now, it will not matter, does not logically undermine its significance today. Likewise, what matters in a million years from now (let’s say for aliens colonizing earth after our species) does not matter at all now, but this does not mean that their significance in that future is undermined. Also, if a life that is finite and short does not matter, extending it will only give us an infinitely long and meaningless life. Being large or small, short or long lived does not change the absurdity of life. Human life could be absurd or not, and these time-space issues will remain orthogonal to its absurdity.

 It seems, according to Nagel, that we can understand and use the concepts like “mattering,” “significance” and “absurdity” in our ordinary languages in a way that is insensitive to time, space and finitude of death. So, if the folk expressions of the absurd seem to treat this concept as if it is highly sensitive to its invariance over time and space, then these folk usages are not using this concept of ordinary language consistently. Even though sometimes it is suggested by our language usage that what matters is what does not vary (across time and space), but the conceptual capacity of our natural languages enables us to have a concept of what matters, but more or less varies (Nagel does not dwell on how and why our ordinary language has this conceptual capacity for registering what matters but varies. This is an important point that I will turn to in the Sect. 2)

1-2 folk absurdity: arguments from “chain of actions-justification”

Another inconsistent folk argument for absurdity could be described as “the argument from long chain of actions.” This argument could be articulated in the following way:

1.     Whatever we are, a chain of actions where each action is justified as a tool to get to the next action, and the whole chain of actions is justifiable because of the goal that it wants to achieve.

2.     Human life is composed of a set of such short or domain-specific chains of actions justified with short-term and domain-specific goals.

3.     For human life to not be absurd, all these short chains should be organized into a single long chain with a final goal unifying all the life.

4.     There is no ultimate goal to human life that is valuable in itself and does not need a justification by another goal.

 

Ø  Human life is absurd.

Nagel takes issue with the third premise of this argument. He questions whether we really need to understand all of the short chains and short-term goals as justifiable and meaningful within the single long chain of the life. He mentions some short-term goals and actions that are self-justifying and do not need to be situated in their place within the grand long chain to be justified. For example, saving a kid from being burned on the stove, taking aspirin for a headache, or going to an exhibition are just short-term self-justifying goals without need for a larger context and purpose.  Nagel argues that even if we want to locate these short chains within a relatively longer one, we still need to posit some relatively long-term goals as self-justifying, otherwise we will face infinite regress, and people will never be motivated enough to engage in life. For Nagel, the very fact that this set of short self-justifying chains exist shows that there is no need for a single long chain for human life to be meaningful.

1-3 philosophical absurdity

Now, those of us who want life to not be absurd might tell themselves: “finally, yes, life is meaningful, thank you Mr. Nagel!” Nagel’s response to such cheerful reaction would have probably been this “Not so fast.” It is true that life is not absurd because of the reasons that folk arguments believe, however, it is absurd for other philosophical reasons. He introduces two sets of reasons for the absurdity of life: 1) conventional reasons for absurdity of some lives, 2) universal reasons for philosophical absurdity of all human life. In the first case, there are some contingent and unfortunate events that take away some goals or the possibility of reaching some goals in our personal projects and make our lives temporarily or permanently. For example, a superstar football player or wrestler becomes cripples and lose the chance of participating in activity which they draw a lot of meaning and motivation from. In the latter, however, no unfortunate accident needs to happen in life. Rather, one’s life is philosophically absurd by virtue of being a human and participating in the universal human condition. Nagel is dismissive of the conventional absurdity and thinks that there is nothing philosophical interesting about it (we will come back to this point in Sect 2). Instead, he focuses on the philosophical universal absurdity of human life. He proposes his formulation of philosophical absurdity, his solution for it, and compares it with Camus’s formulation and solution in his The Myth of Sisyphus.

Nagel starts from the fact that in ordinary language we normally call situations absurd that there is a discrepancy between our aspirations and expectations and the reality. We fight these situations by either changing our expectations, changing the reality, or removing ourselves from that situation. These situations in life are situations of conventional absurdity and even if we cannot remove ourselves from it, we can imagine ways to do that even though we do not have access to those ways for some reasons. Universal absurdity, on the other hand, is not the absurdity of specific situations, rather, the general inescapable absurdity of the whole human life and the discrepancy between our expectations and the reality of life is necessary.

Nagel thinks that Camus's articulation of the absurdity is not universal and philosophical enough, and it still has some elements of conventional absurdity. Camus is understood to claim that human life is absurd because (for some reason) the world always fails to meet our demands and there will always be a discrepancy between what humans (individually and collectively) strive for and what they can achieve (that is a frustrating failure).  Nagel thinks that this is still too optimistic because it is still possible to imagine a conceivable world where the world does not fail to meet our demands. Nagel's articulation of the absurdity is much more pessimistic. Under his formulation, there is no conceivable world (no matter how ideal it is) where human life is not philosophically absurd, as long as human cognitive capacities remain the same in that world.

For Nagel, universal absurdity lies between two inseparable cognitive attitudes that humans are endowed with. On the one hand, our tendency to take our lives and our decisions seriously (“inevitability of the seriousness”). On the other hand, our perceptual and reflective possibility to take a step back and see those goals that we strive for and make our lives meaningful are both arbitrary and epistemically ungrounded and open to doubt (inevitability of reflective detachment).

Let’s start from the inevitability of seriousness. Nagel argues that human affairs are principally in such a way that by the virtue of making a choice, we already have to take up some degree of seriousness and take ourselves and those things seriously. In dealing with life, we have to always put in some energy, attention, and make meaningful choices, and hence become attached to our lives as a serious matter.

On the other hand, we have the possibility of taking a reflective detachment stand toward life. In taking this step, we see how final goals and justifications that we hold dear are arbitrary, that is, had we been born in a different situation (time and place) and faced a different set of events in life, we would not have taken these things seriously, cared about them, or even be aware of them. Also, we can see the fact that we find these goals reasonable is not because of absolute certainty, rather, because we have found it convincing to stop the process of inquiry at a certain point. We just considered X to be a self-justifying goal for our life, not because X is fundamentally self-justifying and one cannot question what justifies X itself, rather because we just decided to stop at that point and not go further. Moreover, we cannot give this reflective detachment and its doubts back. If we experience it just once (and as an inherently human cognitive attitude, we will experience it sooner than later), then even if we consciously decide to avoid it, we are still aware of it and we can still see our rational for avoiding it is an arbitrary and epistemically ungrounded decision. It is not up to will to avoid the reflective detachment stance.

Still, despite these inevitable self-doubting reflective moments, we have to go back to the inevitable seriousness of life. We know that these things in life that we take seriously are not really serious, but we still have to take them seriously. This contradictory situation is the inevitable universal absurdity of human life. You do not have to go a million in the future or another coroner of this vast cosmos to see the absurdity of human life. It is enough to reflect on our cognitive attitudes and see the insignificance and absurdity of human life. Unlike Comus, for Nagel the collision that brings about absurdity is within us and not between the world and our expectations.

1-4. Solutions for philosophical absurdity

At the end of his paper, Nagel considers different solutions for the painful and sobering experience of realizing and being aware of the universal absurdity of human life. Escaping this experience is a non-starter because one cannot intentionally and willfully avoid doubting and deceive oneself. Another way is to avoid taking life seriously like an oriental religion, but that is still taking oneself seriously (putting effort and energy into asceticism) and hence a self-defeating strategy.

Camus also condemns escapism. He holds the solution is to acknowledge the absurdity and failure of human life, but still affirm defiance in the face of this fate. This, supposedly, gives us certain nobility and authenticity. This, for Nagel, is too romantic and self-pitying and not at all relevant reaction. As he puts it, there is no need to “evoke a defiant contempt of fate that allows us to feel brave or proud. Such dramatics, even if carried on in private, betray a failure to appreciate the cosmic unimportance of the situation.” (Nagel 1971, 727).

Instead of Camus’ heroism, Nagel resorts to good old liberal doctrine of intellectual humility and reasonable pluralism and doubt. He argues that there is no reason to consider our experience of absurdity as a painful experience.  It is one of the most human things about us to “transcend ourselves in thoughts.” Absurdity, as part of the human condition, helps us to understand our true situation and be modest in our claims and aspiration. Like a good old classical liberal, Nagel argues that absurdity gives us the chance to be ironic, that is, to not take ourselves and ideas too seriously, accept our limitations and live ironically.

Now, before turning to criticisms of Nagel's argument, let’s unpack what his ironic solution would look like in real life examples. Consider some people who have chosen a single unifying self-justifying goal for their lives (some of his examples are the progress of history, serving society, science, or participating in the glory of god). Now, to be ironic is to acknowledge the absurdity of these “noble” goals like the goals of our personal project. For Nagel, this does not mean to refute or put aside these goals. Rather, to know that they are arbitrary, groundless and only significant under the limitation of human conditions. These goals could exist independently of humans and could be significant independent of humans. Nagel is not committed to refute this possibility in his argument. Rather, if these goals are going to be meaningful, they should be understood within the domains of human understanding and cognitive capacity. As soon as the human understanding gets involved, the inevitable cognitive attitudes of seriousness and self-doubt will come into play. Therefore, we cannot treat them as ultimate and safe sources of meaning and motivations. Rather, we have to take an ironic stance toward them. In other words, for Nagel, even if God, or any other higher being or goal exists, and even if that higher being is the source of significance and meaning in itself, it will not change the universal absurdity of human life. We cannot be sure that they are more than arbitrary postulations, really exist, and that these higher sources of significance and meaning still have to be understood through the limitation of human cognition and situation. We still have chosen these higher or noble goals through an arbitrary and epistemically ungrounded process.

Section Two: Problems of Nagel’s Ironic Absurdism

To recap, we know Nagel’s position on the inevitable absurdity of human life. Arguments from minuteness and from the long chain of action-justifications fail. Variability and finitude across time and space is orthogonal to the significance of human enterprise. Short-term self-justifying goals and chains of action exist, and their justification is as arbitrary as the justification of the so-called noble and unifying goal. Moreover, philosophical absurdity has nothing to do with conventional absurdities of contingent everyday life. Philosophical absurdity is inevitable and should be approached by an ironic attitude.

Now, in this section I will take issue with two aspects of his argument. Firstly, I will argue that his treatment of folk absurdity is too dismissive. Folk or standard articulation of absurdity might be distorted and eternalize a reformable form of absurdity, but it could also allude to a genuine problem. Secondly, I will take issue with his distinction between philosophical and conventional absurdity. Finally, drawing on David Chalmers' famous distinction between hard and soft problem of mind, I distinguish between three problems of absurdity. Hard problem, soft problem and non-problem of absurdity. I will discuss each of them during the course of criticizing Nagel’s argument.

2-1 Where the folk understanding of absurdity does not fail?

Nagel argues that the argument from minuteness fails because things can matter independently of time and space. I agree with this judgment. However, I think it is also important to note that the fact that we can use this concept in this way is not just a naturally given fact of language. One could easily imagine language and cultures where things matter only because they make sense in a divine design of time, space, and after-life. In fact, in most human cultures before the modern times and industrialization, for something to matter or have significance, it should be related to divinity, eternity, and spirituality in one or another way. Just one example will suffice to hammer this point home. Even in contemporary Arabic and Persian language, the terms used for truth and meaning (Haqiqat [حقیقت] and Ma'na [معنا]) are strongly associated with and understood in terms of divinity and spirituality (Haq [حق] and Ma'naviyat [معنویت]). The fact that Modern speakers of these languages, most other human languages, can understand significance and mattering independent of eternal and invariant meaning is the result of the fall of the pre-modern political and economic system and rise of new societies with new class composition and social dynamics. In other words, the modern linguistic usage of the terms “significance” and “meaningful” are the result of a culture shaped by the industrial revolutions, political revolutions and new relations of production, new legal and political arrangements that allowed for new forms of individuality and autonomy in constructing personal and collective identities.

Now, this historical-linguistic fact about concepts of significance and meaningfulness is important because it shows that there is no general logical or conceptual necessary truth about what is the right way to use a concept and what is the right intuition to have about the correct usage of a concept in our ordinary languages. This resonates with Nagel’s own point about how we arbitrarily decide to stop the process of inquiry and take the certain statement as necessary true. Here, Nagel takes his intuitions about correct usage of these terms as primary and given. Now, this means that pre-modern thinkers and poets who have contemplated about the absurdity through themes of the argument from minuteness were not just dumb. It is not too hard to figure out some relation of logical entailment. It would have been easy for them to see that there is no logical entailment between minuteness of something in the scale of time and space and its significance, had they had our modern conceptual and linguistic framework. One of these pre-modern thinkers who is well-known for his uncompromising philosophical short poems about the absurdity of human life is the Medieval Persian thinker and poet Omar Khayyam (1048-1131). Khayyam was a great mathematician, logician, scientist and astronomer of his age. He also left a collection of short poems (called Rubaiyat or quatrains) which is unique in the literary history of Iran and the world in that it is dedicated uncompromisingly to deep reflections on the absurdity of human life. It is not at all an explanation to think that Khayyam just did not notice a simple relation of logical-conceptual entailment as highlighted by Nagel. It is obvious to explain this difference in judgment between Khayyam and Nagel based on their belonging to different linguistic communities with different conceptual frameworks or rules of using certain terms, life meaning, and absurdity. We are living in the modern age, like Nagel, and hence we can have a concept of meaning and absurdity that Khayyam and his contemporaries could not have. However, this does not mean that they were wrong, and the standard or folk understanding of absurdity (as expressed in Khayyam) fails. Rather, Khayyam’s specific linguistic and conceptual tradition could have enabled him to understand some other aspect of absurdity that is not easily accessible to our modern sensibility. I will come back to this point at the end of this section where I discuss the hard problem of absurdity.[1]

So folk argument form minuteness does not simply fail, as Nagel argues. Now turn to his discussion of the argument from long chain of action-justification. Again, I agree with him that in the modern cultures and languages we have the conceptual capacity to talk about certain self-justifying goals and short chains of action. However, this is a truism. What really brings about ordinary people’s frustration, disorientation and feeling absurd is not that they cannot find a set of self-justifying goals. Instead, how they decide and justify (individually or collectively) those goals and how these decision shape their social life is the real source of modern absurdity. As Aristotle has pointed out in the first book of the Nicomachean Ethics, humans use actions and things as a mean for a higher good, and the candidate for this higher good could be different things. One candidate seems to favor the most is the eudaimonic life realized through polis, that is, a flourished and just political life of society. In this political life, people can collectively and collaboratively think about, justify, and organize their short-chain and long-chain goals of their personal and social life. In this way, they can be more sure that where they decide to stop at a certain goal and consider it as self-justifying in the short or long-term, this decision is justified through the collaborative rationality of the political community, and it does not contradict and badly influence other people’s ability to have flourished meaningful life. Now, Marx is a diehard Aristotelian in this regard. He remarks in his Grundrisse (1973 [1858]) that, “the human being is in the most literal sense a zoon politikon, not merely a gregarious animal, but an animal which can individuate itself only in the midst of society.” Production by an isolated individual outside society “is as much of an absurdity as the development of language without human beings living together and talking to each other. (Marx 1973, 84) Moreover, in his Economic and Philosophical Manuscript of 1848, he deals with the main problem with capitalism, alienation and devaluation of the meaning of life. Marx argues that the estrangement of life activity and estrangement from species changes for humans:

 […] the life of the species into a means of individual life. First, it estranges the life of the species and individual life, and secondly, it makes individual life in its abstract form the purpose of the life of the species, likewise in its abstract and estranged form. (Collected Work, vol 3, 276)

the separation is between “individual life” and the collective “life of the species”, leading to the repression of human life's potentialities. This leads to the dominance of an “abstract form of individual life” (unbridled egoism) over the collective aspect of life. Hence the collective aspect of life would be degraded and treated just as means for the egoist individual life. While the right and balanced relationship between these two aspects would be when, “in the place of the old bourgeois society with its classes and its class antagonisms, there will be an association in which the free development of each is the condition for the free development of all.” (Collected Work, vol 6, 506)

This aspect of the problem, that is, the social roots of modern nihilism and absurdism, totally escapes Nagel’s understanding of the absurdity. It is true that folk expression of absurdity of life is not always aware of its socially mediated roots. These expressions might mystify and eternalize absurdity as something unchangeable. For example, consider someone who thinks becoming a successful and wealthy banker is the ultimate goal in life, and then at moments of weakness they contemplate on how arbitrary and absurd this self-justifying goal is. This experience of absurdity is socially mediated. They have set this goal without the collective rationality of the political community, and following it leads to deprivation of others from their life-chances and flourishing. Setting and individualistic goal for life in an isolated way (unbridled egoism) and the vices and estrangement from others that it brings about devalue and degrade human life for this banker and other people. It limits the capacity of humans for social rationality and social decision-making. Capitalism is a machine of absurdity and nihilism for Marx because it gives the “abstract individuality” of people like the banker in our example, to shape the social life in a significant way.

 As we will see, Nagel’s negligence of the socially mediated roots of folk absurdity or nihilism has important and problematic implications for his own philosophical formulation of absurdity.

2-2 The failed distinction between conventional and philosophical absurdity

Nagel draws a distinction between conventional and philosophical-universal absurdity. The former happens for contingent reasons and can make our life absurd temporarily or permanently. Still, it is conceivable to imagine a world where that conventional absurdity does not hold. In contrast, philosophical absurdity is universal and cannot be removed from the human condition. Nagel thinks that the former is not a real philosophical problem and the universal absurdity is the only philosophically interesting problem.

If we bring into the picture the socially mediated roots of absurdity, this distinction falls apart. Conventional absurdity has two problems. It conflates sadness and disappointment with the experience of absurdity. Remember the example of the superstar athlete who becomes crippled. They might feel deeply sad about the loss. But in a fair and flourishing society, they have enough support to not feel isolated, connect with other humans, and flourish new talents and capacities in their life (painting or music for example). In any case, in Marx’s humanistic picture of a just and flourishing society, humans do not follow their interests and talents one dimensionally, rather they stay multi-dimensional.

So what Nagel calls conventional absurdity is not at all absurdity unless it is mediated by a social world that represses human capacity for sociality, rationality and harmonic personal and public flourishment. Moreover, what Nagel calls philosophical and universal absurdity is not inevitable absurdity at all. Our justification for short-term and long-term self-justifying goals and how they can be harmonized together will be arbitrary and doubtful if it is carried out in an isolated and individualistic way. In contrast, if our justifications are mediated and harmonized through the process of the collective deliberation of the political community. This does not give ultimate non-arbitrary justifications, but it gives us ones that are mediated and shaped through the process of social rationality. From experience we can tell that humans feel more certain and stratified with these types of rationality. For example, Helen Longino, feminist philosopher of science, in her The Fate of Knowledge, argues that the objectivity and non-arbitrariness of our scientific knowledge is achieved through a social process of collective knowledge production and collective justification in equal and well-structured scientific communities. As a result, scientists do not need to go through existential crisis about the certainty and justifiability of their knowledge. Instead, they are sure that their knowledge is certain as much as socially mediated human certainty can achieve. Similarly, members of Marx’s humanist eudemonic political community could be certain that their posited self-justifying goals are not ad-hoc and arbitrary as much as socially mediated justification and rationality can achieve. Humans have a better time sitting with this type of certainty and do not freak out at the prospect of possible collective revisions and reconsiderations. Nagel’s picture assumes (for no good reason) the impossibility of human social rationality on self-justifying goals and harmonizing them within the boundaries of reasonable pluralism. This political community, unlike a Rawlsian liberal political community, does not give rise to an anti-perfectionist state that avoids any doctrine of good life. Instead, it allows for minimal agreement on substantive issues like regard for human sociality, democratic reasoning of allocation of social wealth and productive forces beyond the tyranny of exploitative private control over the socially produced wealth.

To recap this part of the argument, what Nagel calls philosophical absurdity could be a non-problem (in a eudemonic society) and soft reformable problem (in a capitalist society). And what he calls conventional absurdity could be a soft problem or sometimes a hard problem (as I will discuss in the next section).

2.3. Hard, Soft and Non-Problem of Absurdity

As argued above, Nagel’s universal and philosophical absurdity emanating from our reflection on the arbitrariness of our decision about self-justifying goals is a non-problem or at best a soft and socially reformable problem of absurdity. Humans (especially in modern cultures) do not find it worrisome if their justifications in scientific and political communities are not absolute but socially mediated. On the other hand, what Nagel calls conventional absurdity is a soft problem of absurdity. Finally, what Nagel calls incoherent folk absurdism could actually be understood to be alluding to a hard problem of absurdity or what I call Khayyam’s problem of absurdity.

Nagel is not coherent about this hard problem. At the beginning of the paper, where he is refuting the standard and folk arguments for absurdity (argument from minuteness), he holds that cosmic insignificance is not a problem for the human project of following meaningful goals in their lives. However, by the end of the paper, where he is rejecting Camus’ heroic contempt solution, he brings back the notion of cosmic insignificance and argues that such dramatics is meaningless in the face of our cosmic insignificance. While he argued earlier that the real universal absurdity is an internal collision and has nothing to do with our cosmic insignificance.

As I understand it, Khayyam’s hard problem of absurdity (coming from our cosmic insignificance) is not answerable through pointing out a simple fact about logical entailment (as Nagel thinks). Rather, given how we use our language, it could be not only a real but hard problem. In our modern languages, we have the conceptual capacity to talk about the significance of our projects regardless of how fragile and small they are. Still, it is conceivable for us to use the terms significance and meaningfulness in a way that they imply an expectation. An expectation that what we find just, virtuous, and flourishing social human life resonates with nature and the universe. That is, it is harmonic and protected and will not be disrupted by mere accidents (the notorious example of an asteroid hitting the earth). This hope is a legitimate hope. However, we can never be sure that this hope will be realized.

Hard problem of absurdity is not as much a problem as a source of inspiration and reflection. It is the understanding that even if we feel satisfied in socially eudemonic and flourishing life, we are still very fragile and finite in cosmic terms. This awareness of finality and fragility is not an obstacle in the way of our social process of justification of noble goals and following them. Rather, it will inform this process. We should understand and follow these self-justifying and satisfying goals with humility and awareness of our fragility as individuals and as an animal species.

In this sense, Khayyam’s absurdity is not a source of distress. We could still have a meaningful personal and social eudemonic life even if an asteroid hit the earth and destroyed that eudemonic society forever. The meaningfulness of that life will not be perished by its cosmic insignificance. Khayyam’s absurdity is not a universal acid to threaten everything. Instead of a source for distress, it is a source for wonder, humility and acceptance of human fragility.

Section Three: Against Heroism and liberal Irony

If my assessments are correct. We should not waste our time with the non-problem of absurdity. We should accept but not feel distressed by the hard problem of absurdity. Then, it follows that the main problem of absurdity that faces us is the soft problem, that is, moving toward a society that allows for eudemonic social life. Given this picture, I will conclude by assessing different solutions to the problem of absurdity and offer my own solution to the soft problem of absurdity that I call socialist humor in comparison to Nagel’s liberal ironic attitude.

Given the picture that I have drawn, Camus' treatment of absurdity is much closer to the reality of how actual people experience socially mediated absurdities than that of Nagel. Nagel takes absurdity and internalizes in a way that is not a collision between human hopes and the world, but an unchangeable internal collision. However, for Camus absurdity is still a between humans and the world. Still, Camus ends up eternalizing this collision as something irremediable. As if the world is just naturally hostile to human meaningful projects. However, it must be clear by now that this neglects the social roots of absurdities in class societies, especially in capitalist societies dominated by alienation and unbridled egoism and impoverished deliberative rationality.

 If there is no eternalized absurdity (as Nagel or Camus understand it, then there is no need for their solutions (heroic contempt or ironic acceptance). What we need instead is an optimistic and militant ethos to fight back against the social arrangements that make our lives absurd and not worth living. We need a militant ethos to change it collectively and bring about an eudaimonic life through the resistance of the oppressed. One does not have to answer the substantive questions facing eudemonic political community to achieve such a community. Rather, one has to remove capitalist and class relation barriers on this collective deliberation.

 Under my view, fighting fascism and the ideology of hatred, where there is the threat of it, is always the most meaningful thing that one can do with their life. There is no way in which one can take an ironic stand toward its fight against fascism. In his famous Novel, Under Western Eyes (1911), Joseph Conrad put these warning words in the mouth of one of his characters:

“Remember, Razumov, that women, children, and revolutionists hate irony, which is the negation of all saving instincts, of all faith, of all devotion, of all action.” (Konrad 1911, p 183)

Here, Conrad, like Nagel, is reminding us of the dangers of taking oneself too seriously and the benefits of having an ironic sense. As I mentioned earlier, fighting for eudemonic life does not involve having a strong substantive view about the meaning of life. Instead, it involves participating in collective and democratic struggle against the exploitative and class relations that take away the possibility of collective deliberation about self-justifying goals. This warning of Konrad and Nagel comes from a place of liberal pessimism and apologism for capitalism than an acclaimed place of wisdom. Revolutionary men and women who are fighting oppression and deprivation of their lives have every right to not have a sense of ironic self-doubt. This is a misplaced warning. There is not that much discrepancy between the danger of revolutionary falling for bigotry (limiting social and collaborative reasoning) and the apologist of the status quo (liberal or conservative) to fall for bigoted and arrogant ironic attitude.

Conclusion: Socialist Humor Against Liberal Irony

Let me conclude by shortly discussing what complicates my picture of collective fighting against what makes our lives absurd and alienated. My proposal seems to be pretty straightforward: Don’t mind the non-problem and the hard problem of absurdity, let’s fight the social roots of soft absurdities, that is, what deprives us of the possibility of setting and following self-justifying goals through social rationality of the political community.

Now, it seems that my proposal implies that in the absence of a eudemonic social life, one should dedicate one’s life to the long-term goal of establishing such societies. However, this is only one long-term goal among others. In the absence of eudemonic societies, people can still lead eudemonic lives by following self-justifying goals (at least in their personal lives) that are possibly defendable in the court of a hypothetical rational political community.  For example, consider scientists who are contributing human knowledge or Doctors Without Borders while being mindful of not engaging (as much as they could) in exploitative relationships. There is a limit to how much these personal projects could be meaningful in the absence of a mutual interplay between flourishing personal and political aspects of social life. Still, this limit does not change the fact that these lives are eudemonic.

Given this diversity of forms of leading eudemonic life in the absence of eudemonic societies, then the question arises. What if I fail in these truly meaningful projects? What if we do not get a chance or lose our chance to lead one or another way of leading eudemonic lives like political fight against capitalism or being a doctor serving your principles?

Are we left with a distressing absurdity? Here is where my concept of socialist humor comes into play. To explain this attitude, I draw on Oscar Wilde. In his Lady Windermere’s Fan (1892), Wilde has this famous line that is quoted a lot in pop culture.

Lady Windermere.  Why do you talk so trivially about life, then?

Lord Darlington.  Because I think that life is far too important a thing ever to talk seriously about it.  [Moves up C.]

Duchess of Berwick.  What does he mean?  Do, as a concession to my poor wits, Lord Darlington, just explain to me what you really mean.

Lord Darlington.  [Coming down back of table.]  I think I had better not, Duchess.  Nowadays to be intelligible is to be found out.  Good-bye!  [Shakes hands with Duchess.]  And now—[goes up stage] Lady Windermere, good-bye.  I may come to-night, mayn’t I?  Do let me come.

 

Life is too important to be taken seriously. Notice that this remark is at the opposite side of liberal ironic wisdom. There, life and its goals and hopes are too ad hoc and arbitrary to be taken seriously. Here, the reason not to take the existing deprived form of life (imposed under capitalism on individuals) seriously is that life is inherently too important. This is the insight that I want to highlight. Human experience is a unique and finite experience, but it is inherently meaningful and could be led in eudemonic ways. However, under an alienated social life, our lives could be partially influenced by unjustified idolized goals (seeking money) or it can be too messy for us to wave its short chains into a single long chain of action-justification. This could be a distressing form of absurdity. However, a socialist or eudemonic humor faces this distress with a humorous attitude. Here humor is not laughing at ourselves, rather laughing at an alienated and deprived social world. It is realizing that its imposed goals (even though sometimes we have to follow) are not really the ultimately meaningful goals. It is acknowledging our limited power and fragile will to lead a eudemonic life under a hostile social world. Our failures in imposed or genuine projects of seeking goals should not distress us. We still have a chance of trying again and enjoying an eudemonic life against what the alienated social relations impose on us as ad hoc and unreflect goals. Holding this chance and being aware of how important it is (knowing how important human life is) enables us to not take the imposed arbitrary goals of life under capitalism seriously.

 

Farid Saberi

9 March 2025, London, Ontario, Canada

Western University

Rotman Institute of Philosophy.

 

 

 

 

 

 



[1] Notice that the relativistic conclusion does not directly follow from comparing two different linguistic and conceptual traditions. One does not have to say that there is no general fact about absurdity that is shared between Khayyam’s age and our modern age. Rather, one could equally interpret this as different sensibilities and abilities to better understand or focus on different aspects of the problem of absurdity. I will defend this interpretation in this section.

Comments

Popular Posts